In mathematics, a set is said to be closed under some operation if performance of that operation on members of the set always produces a unique member of the same set. For example, the real numbers are closed under subtraction, but the natural numbers are not: 3 and 8 are both natural numbers, but the result of 3 − 8 is not. 0 is a closed set under multiplication.
Similarly, a set is said to be closed under a collection of operations if it is closed under each of the operations individually.
A set that is closed under an operation or collection of operations is said to satisfy a closure property. Often a closure property is introduced as an axiom, which is then usually called the axiom of closure. Note that modern set-theoretic definitions usually define operations as maps between sets, so adding closure to a structure as an axiom is superfluous, though it still makes sense to ask whether subsets are closed. For example, the set of real numbers is closed under subtraction, where (as mentioned above) its subset of natural numbers is not.
When a set S is not closed under some operations, one can usually find the smallest set containing S that is closed. This smallest closed set is called the closure of S (with respect to these operations). For example, the closure under subtraction of the set of natural numbers, viewed as a subset of the real numbers, is the set of integers. An important example is that of topological closure. The notion of closure is generalized by Galois connection, and further by monads.
Note that the set S must be a subset of a closed set in order for the closure operator to be defined. In the preceding example, it is important that the reals are closed under subtraction; in the domain of the natural numbers subtraction is not always defined.
The two uses of the word "closure" should not be confused. The former usage refers to the property of being closed, and the latter refers to the smallest closed set containing one that isn't closed. In short, the closure of a set satisfies a closure property.
Contents |
A set is closed under an operation if that operation returns a member of the set when evaluated on members of the set. Sometimes the requirement that the operation be valued in a set is explicitly stated, in which case it is known as the axiom of closure. For example, one may define a group as a set with a binary product operator obeying several axioms, including an axiom that the product of any two elements of the group is again an element. However the modern definition of an operation makes this axiom superfluous; an n-ary operation on S is just a subset of Sn+1. By its very definition, an operator on a set cannot have values outside the set.
Nevertheless, the closure property of an operator on a set still has some utility. Closure on a set does not necessarily imply closure on all subsets. Thus a subgroup of a group is a subset on which the binary product and the unary operation of inversion satisfy the closure axiom.
An operation of a different sort is that of finding the limit points of a subset of a topological space (if the space is first-countable, it suffices to restrict consideration to the limits of sequences but in general one must consider at least limits of nets). A set that is closed under this operation is usually just referred to as a closed set in the context of topology. Without any further qualification, the phrase usually means closed in this sense. Closed intervals like [1,2] = {x: 1 ≤ x ≤ 2} are closed in this sense.
A partially ordered set is downward closed (and also called a lower set) if for every element of the set all smaller elements are also in it; this applies for example for the real intervals (−∞, p) and (−∞, p], and for an ordinal number p represented as interval [ 0, p); every downward closed set of ordinal numbers is itself an ordinal number.
Upward closed and upper set are defined similarly.
The notion of a closure can be generalized for an arbitrary binary relation R ⊆ S×S, and an arbitrary property P in the following way: the P closure of R is the least relation Q ⊆ S×S that contains R (i.e. R ⊆ Q) and for which property P holds (i.e. P(Q) is true). For instance, one can define the symmetric closure as the least symmetric relation containing R. This generalization is often encountered in the theory of rewriting systems, where one often uses more "wordy" notions such as the reflexive transitive closure R*—the smallest preorder containing R, or the reflexive transitive symmetric closure R≡—the smallest equivalence relation containing R, and therefore also known as the equivalence closure. For arbitrary P and R, the P closure of R need not exist. In the above examples, these exist because reflexivity, transitivity and symmetry are closed under arbitrary intersections. In such cases, the P closure can be directly defined as the intersection of all sets with property P containing R.[1]
Given an operation on a set X, one can define the closure C(S) of a subset S in X to be the smallest subset closed under that operation that contains S as a subset. For example, the closure of a subset of a group is the subgroup generated by that set.
The closure of sets with respect to some operation defines a closure operator on the subsets of X. The closed sets can be determined from the closure operator; a set is closed if it is equal to its own closure. Typical structural properties of all closure operations are:
An object that is its own closure is called closed. By idempotency, an object is closed if and only if it is the closure of some object.
These three properties define an abstract closure operator. Typically, an abstract closure acts on the class of all subsets of a set.